위상에서의 필터

Filters in topology
상위 집합{ 4인 집합 { 1,,, 상위 집합이 {1인 집합 X : {\의 전원 집합은 진한 녹색으로 채색된다.그것은 필터일 뿐 아니라 심지어 주요한 필터일 수도 있다.연두색 원소도 포함시켜 더 큰 비중격 필터} 까지 확장할 수 있기 때문에 울트라필터가 아니다. } X을(를) 더 이상 연장할 수 없기 때문에 초여광필터다.

수학의 하위 분야인 위상 필터위상학적 공간을 연구하고 융합, 연속성, 콤팩트성 등과 같은 모든 기본 위상학적 개념을 정의하는 데 사용될 수 있다.필터는 특정 집합의 하위 집합의 특수 패밀리인 것으로서, 좌/우, 무한대, 점 또는 집합, 그리고 그 밖의 여러 가지 유형의 기능 한계를 정의하기 위한 공통 프레임워크도 제공한다.울트라필터라고 불리는 특수한 유형의 필터는 많은 유용한 기술적 특성을 가지고 있고 그것들은 종종 임의의 필터 대신에 사용될 수 있다.

필터는 프리필터(필터 베이스라고도 함)와 필터 서브베이스라는 일반화를 가지며, 이 모든 것은 위상 전체에 걸쳐 자연스럽고 반복적으로 나타난다.예를 들어 근린 필터/베이스/하위 데이터베이스 및 통일성을 들 수 있다.모든 필터는 프리필터고 둘 다 필터 서브베이스다.모든 프리필터와 필터 서브베이스는 고유한 가장 작은 필터에 포함되어 있으며, 필터 서브베이스는 생성된다고 한다.이는 필터와 프리필터 사이의 관계를 설정하는데, 이 두 개념 중 기술적으로 더 편리한 개념 중 하나를 사용할 수 있도록 종종 이용될 수 있다.notion , {\\,\로 표시된 세트 제품군에는 하나의 개념(필터, 프리필터 등)이 다른 개념 대신 사용될 수 있거나 사용할 수 없는 정확한 시기와 방법을 결정하는 데 도움이 되는 특정 사전 주문이 있다.This preorder's importance is amplified by the fact that it also defines the notion of filter convergence, where by definition, a filter (or prefilter) converges to a point if and only if where 그 지점의 근린 필터다.결과적으로, 종속성은 클러스터 포인트와 기능의 한계와 같이 융합과 관련된 많은 개념에서도 중요한 역할을 한다.In addition, the relation which denotes and is expressed by saying that is subordinate to also establishes a 이(가) 에 대한 관계(즉, 후순위라고 하는 관계 , 는 "후순위"의 아날로그 필터에 대한 것이다.

필터는 1937년[1][2] 앙리 카르탄에 의해 소개되었고 이후 부르바키가 1922년 E. H. 무어H. L. 스미스에 의해 개발된 그물의 유사한 개념의 대안으로 그들의 책 Topologie Généale에 의해 사용되었다.필터는 또한 시퀀스네트 수렴의 개념을 특성화하는 데 사용될 수 있다.하지만 unlike[노트 1]순서와 네트 통합 필터 통합 전적으로 위상 공간 X{X\displaystyle}의 하위 집합의 조건이 융합의 완전히 위상 공간 고유의 것이다 생각을 제공한다. 실제로, 위상 공간의 범주 동등하게 전적으로 측면에서 정의될 수 있고 정의된다.필터s. 모든 네트는 표준 필터를 유도하고, 한 번에 모든 필터는 표준 그물을 유도하며, 이 유도 그물(resp. 유도 필터)이 원래 필터(resp. net)와 동일한 경우에만 한 지점으로 수렴된다.이러한 특성화는 클러스터 지점과 같은 다른 많은 정의에도 적용된다.이러한 관계들은 필터와 그물 사이를 전환할 수 있게 해주며, 또한 종종 이 두 가지 개념(필터 또는 그물) 중 어떤 것이 당면한 문제에 더 편리한지를 선택할 수 있게 해준다.그러나 "하위 네트워크"가 가장 널리 사용되는 정의(WillardKelley가 제공한 정의) 중 하나를 사용하여 정의된다고 가정하면, 일반적으로 이 관계는 하위 필터와 서브넷으로 확장되지 않는다. 왜냐하면 아래에 자세히 설명했듯이 필터/하위-필터 관계를 설명할 수 없는 하위 필터가 존재하기 때문이다.그러나, 해당 네트워크/서브넷 관계의 측면에서, 이 문제는 AA-서브넷의 정의인 "서브넷"의 덜 흔하게 접하는 정의를 사용함으로써 해결될 수 있다.

따라서 필터/프리필터와 이 단일 사전 주문서 은(는) 위상학적 공간(근린 필터 사용), 근린 기반, 수렴, 다양한 기능 제한, 연속성, 콤팩트함, 시퀀스(순차 필터 사용), th와 같은 기본 위상학적 개념을 원활하게 결합하는 프레임워크를 제공한다.e 필터 "변형성"(변형성), 균일한 공간 등에 해당하며, 그렇지 않으면 상대적으로 이질적인 것처럼 보이고 관계가 덜 명확한 개념이다.

동기

필터의 전형적인 예

필터의 전형적 예로는 위상학적 , ) ,{\ x}의x {\}에 N {\}(x 주변 필터인데, 정의상x .{\x}의 모든 인접 영역으로 구성된 집합이다.d of some given point is any subset whose topological interior contains this point; that is, such that Importantly, neighborhoods are not required to be open sets; those are called open neighborhoods.아래 열거된 근린필터가 공유하는 근본적인 속성은 결국 '필터'의 정의가 되었다. 필터 조건을 모두 충족하는 X 하위 집합 B displaystyle 집합이다.

  1. 비어 있지 않음: ( x), X과 마찬가지로 X 은 항상 및 그 밖의 모든 것)의 이웃);
  2. 세트를 포함하지 않음: ∅ - x 의 인접 항목이 비어 있지 않은 것처럼,
  3. 유한 교차로에 따라 폐쇄됨: , , 그 B {\ B }{\가) 교차하는 것이 다시 x의 주변인 것처럼 말이다.
  4. 위쪽 닫힘:If then – just as any subset of that contains a neighborhood of will necessarily be a neighborhood of X "{\의 정의에 따른다.

세트를 사용하여 시퀀스 수렴 일반화 - 시퀀스 없이 시퀀스 수렴 결정

순서는 정의상 자연수에서 X .{\까지의 지도 → X 대한 원래 위상학적 공간에서의 수렴 개념은 메트릭 공간과 같은 공간의 특정 지점으로 수렴되는 순서의 개념이었다.측정 가능한 공간(또는 더 일반적으로 계산 가능한 공간 또는 Fréchet-Uryson 공간)의 경우 시퀀스는 대개 하위 집합의 폐쇄나 기능의 연속성과 같은 대부분의 위상학적 특성을 특징짓거나 "설명"하기에 충분하다.그러나 폐쇄나 연속성과 같은 기본적인 위상학적 특성조차 설명하기 위해 시퀀스를 사용할 수 없는 공간이 많다.이러한 시퀀스의 실패는 그물이나 필터와 같은 개념을 정의하는 동기였으며, 위상학적 성질을 특징 짓는데 실패하지 않았다.

Nets directly generalize the notion of a sequence since nets are, by definition, maps from an arbitrary directed set into the space A sequence is just a net whose domain is with the natural o갈기갈기 찢기는그물에는 그들만의 융합 개념이 있는데, 이것은 시퀀스 융합의 직접적인 일반화다.

필터는 시퀀스 만 고려하여 다른 방식으로 시퀀스 수렴을 일반화한다.To see how this is done, consider a sequence which is by definition just a function whose value at 은(는) 임의 함수에 일반적으로 사용되는 일반적인 괄호 x () 이(가) 아닌 {\bullet }(로 표시된다.Knowing only the image (sometimes called "the range") of the sequence is not enough to characterize its convergence; multiple sets are needed.필요한 세트는 다음과 같은 것으로 밝혀졌는데,[note 2] 이를 x x_{\꼬리라고 한다

세트는 이 시퀀스의 수렴(또는 비융합)을 완전히 결정하는데, 이 시퀀스는 모든 주변 U이 지점의에 대해 U {\ U이() 모든 를 포함하는 정수 n 이(가) 있는 경우에만 수렴되기 때문이다+ ,(가) 다음과 같이 다시 쓰일 수 있다.

모든 이웃 은(는) 하위 집합으로{ + 1,… {\x_},},\ldots 의 일부 형식을 포함해야 한다.

It is the above characterization that can be used with the above family of tails to determine convergence (or non–convergence) of the sequence Specifically, with these sets in hand, the function is no이 시퀀스의 수렴을 결정하는 데 더 오래 필요함( 에 어떤 토폴로지를 배치하든 상관 없음).이러한 관찰을 일반화함으로써, 「융합」의 개념은 기능에서 집합의 패밀리로 확장될 수 있다.

위의 일련의 꼬리는 일반적으로 필터가 아니라 위쪽으로 닫힘으로써 필터를 "생성"한다.일반적으로 필터가 아니라 상향 폐쇄를 통해 필터를 생성한다(특히, 해당 지점에서 근린 필터를 생성함).이들 가족이 공유하는 속성은 필터 베이스(prefilter)라는 개념으로 이어졌는데, 정의상으로는 필터의 상향 폐쇄만을 통해 필터를 생성하기에 필요한 최소한의 속성을 가지고 있는 모든 제품군이다.

- 장단점 - - 장 - 점

필터와 그물은 각자 장점과 단점을 가지고 있으며, 한 가지 개념을 다른 개념보다 독점적으로 사용할 이유가 없다.[note 3]증명되고 있는 것에 따라, 증거는 다른 개념 대신에 이러한 개념들 중 하나를 사용함으로써 상당히 쉽게 만들어질 수 있다.[3]필터와 그물 모두 주어진 토폴로지를 완전히 특성화하는 데 사용될 수 있다.그물은 시퀀스의 직접적인 일반화로서 종종 시퀀스와 유사하게 사용될 수 있기 때문에, 그물에 대한 학습 곡선은 일반적으로 필터에 대한 그것보다 훨씬 덜 가파르다.그러나 필터, 특히 울트라필터세트이론, 수학논리학, 모델이론(예를 들어 초고성능), 추상대수학,[4] 순서이론, 일반화된 수렴공간, 코우치공간, 초현실수의 정의와 사용 등 위상 외의 용도가 더 많다.

순서와 마찬가지로, 그물망도 기능이기 때문에 기능 장점을 가지고 있다.예를 들어, 시퀀스와 마찬가지로, 네트는 다른 기능에 "플러그인"될 수 있으며, 여기서 "플러그인"은 기능 구성일 뿐이다.기능 및 기능 구성과 관련된 이론은 그물에 적용될 수 있다.한 예로 역한계의 보편적 특성이 있는데, 이는 세트보다는 함수 구성의 관점에서 정의되며 필터와 같은 세트보다는 네트와 같은 기능에 더 쉽게 적용된다(역한계의 두드러진 예는 데카르트 제품이다).는 공간 X{\ X 필터와 밀도가 높은 공간 S X {\S\X.}의 필터 간 전환과 같은 특정 상황에서 사용하기 어려울 수 있다

그물망과 대조적으로 필터(및 프리필터)는 세트 제품군이기 때문에 세트 장점이 있다.예를 들어, 이() 돌출적인 경우, 이미지 - 1( B): {- (): } f under of an arbitrary filter or prefilter is both easily defined and guaranteed to be a prefilter on 's domain, whereas it is less clear how to pullback (unambiguously/without choice) an임의 시퀀스(또는 net) {\을(를) 도메인에서 시퀀스나 그물을 얻을 수 있도록 f {\ f도 주입되어 결과적으로 바이어싱이 되는 경우는 제외되며, 이는 엄격한 요구 사항이다.필터는 고려 중인 매우 위상학적 공간 X의 하위 집합으로 구성되기 때문에 위상학적 세트 작업(폐쇄 또는 내부 등)을 필터를 구성하는 세트에 적용할 수 있다.예를 들어 필터의 모든 세트를 닫는 것이 기능 분석에 유용할 수 있다.기능에 따른 세트의 이미지 또는 사전 이미지에 대한 이론과 결과는 필터를 구성하는 세트에도 적용될 수 있다. 그러한 결과의 예는 개방/폐쇄 세트의 사전 이미지 또는 내부/폐쇄 운영자의 측면에서 연속성 특성 중 하나가 될 수 있다.울트라필터라고 불리는 특수한 유형의 필터는 결과 입증에 크게 도움이 될 수 있는 유용한 특성을 많이 가지고 있다.그물의 한 가지 단점은 도메인을 구성하는 방향 집합에 의존하는 것인데, 일반적으로는 X와 전혀 무관할 수 있다 실제로 주어진 X{\의 그물 등급은 세트(적절한 등급)조차 되기에는 너무 크다. 는 X }의 그물 등급이 너무 크기 때문이다. X은(는) 카디널리티도메인을 가질 수 있다.In contrast, the collection of all filters (and of all prefilters) on is a set whose cardinality is no larger than that of Similar to a topology on a filter on is "intrinsic to "두 구조물이 X{\}의 하위 집합으로 구성되며, 어떤 정의도 에서 구성할 수 없는 집합(: N {\displaysty 또는 시퀀스 및 네트가 필요로 하는 기타 방향 집합)을 필요로 하지 않는다는 점에서.

예단, 표기법 및 기본 개념

In this article, upper case Roman letters like denote sets (but not families unless indicated otherwise) and will denote the power set of A subset of a power set is called a family of sets (or simply, a family) where it is over if it is a subset of Families of sets will be denoted by upper case calligraphy letters such as Whenever these assumptions are needed, then it should be assumed (가) 비어 있지 않고 등이 . X}을를) 넘는 집합 집합 집합 집합입니다

"프리필터"와 "필터 베이스"라는 용어는 동의어로, 상호간에 사용될 것이다.

경쟁 정의 및 표기법에 대한 경고

불행히도 필터 이론에는 다른 작가들에 의해 다르게 정의되는 몇 가지 용어가 있다.여기에는 "필터"와 같은 가장 중요한 용어들이 포함되어 있다.동일한 용어의 서로 다른 정의는 대개 상당한 중첩을 가지지만, 필터(및 포인트 설정 위상)의 기술적 특성 때문에, 그럼에도 불구하고 정의의 이러한 차이는 종종 중요한 결과를 초래한다.수학적 문헌을 읽을 때 필터와 관련된 용어가 저자에 의해 어떻게 정의되는지를 독자들이 확인하는 것이 좋다.이 때문에 이 글에는 이 글에서 사용되는 모든 정의가 명쾌하게 기술되어 있을 것이다.불행히도 필터와 관련된 모든 표기법이 잘 확립되어 있는 것은 아니며 일부 표기법은 문헌에 걸쳐 크게 달라지기 때문에(예를 들어, 한 세트의 모든 프리필터 집합에 대한 표기법) 이러한 경우 이 글은 가장 자기적으로 설명하거나 쉽게 기억되는 표기법을 사용한다.

필터와 프리필터의 이론은 잘 발달되어 있고 정의와 명언이 많으며, 그 중 많은 것들이 현재 이 글이 장황하게 되는 것을 막고 표기법과 정의의 쉬운 룩업을 가능하게 하기 위해 약식으로 나열되어 있다.그들의 중요한 성질은 나중에 설명된다.

설정 작업 정정

세트 ( X ){\displaystyle {B[6][7] {\ 상향 마감 또는 이소톤화는

and similarly the downward closure of is

이름
{\mathcal {B}의
(는) 집합임 의 이중 표시[8]
(는) 집합임 의 추적[8] 에서 로 제한{\{\}{\ B S{\{\에 의해 표시됨
[9] 요소별(세트) 교차로( C 일반적인 교차로임을 나타낸다.
[9] 요소별(세트) 결합( C }컵 일반적인 결합을 나타낸다.
요소별(세트) 뺄셈( C {\ 일반적인 세트 뺄셈을 나타낸다.
의 B 그릴[10]
집합 전원 세트

For any two families declare that if and only if for every there exists some {{F\mathcal}}{\text{그런}}F\subseteq C,}이 사건에서 C{\displaystyle{{C\mathcal}}}F{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}보다}}알이 굵었으며, F{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}}}(또는 하급자)C.{\displaystyle{{C\mathcal}보다}finer 있다.}표기법[11][12][13]다고 한다. F⊢ f}\{\}{{\mathcal }}}}{\c}}}을를) 사용할 수도 있다

두 가족이 B, C{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}{\text{과}}{{C\mathcal}}}mesh,[8] 쓴 B#C,{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}})#{{C\mathcal}},}만약 B∩ C≠ 모든 B∈ B, C∈ C∅.{\displaystyle B\cap C\neq{모든{에 \text \varnothing}}B\in{{B\mathcal}}{\text{과}}C\in{\mat.hca

전체적으로 은(는) 지도가 된다.

이름
[14] - , 의 B 또는 {\{\}{\의 B 이미지
(는) 임의 집합이다. - ,의 S{\ S f {\ 사전
[14] 이미지
(는) 임의 집합이다. S의 S
의 이미지

위상 표기법

( X) . {\{by X)를 으로 집합의 모든 위상 집합을 나타낸다 ( X). X)를 가정해 보십시오

이름
, ) 에서 열린 인접 영역 설정 또는 프리필터[note 4]
( ,) xtau 의 열린 영역 설정 또는 프리필터
,) 에서 S 영역의 설정 또는 필터[note 4]
,) 주변 설정 또는 필터

If then

그물과 꼬리

나는 함께 preorder과{\displaystyle 1세}는≤{\displaystyle \,\leq\와 같이,}(지 않으면 명시적으로 별도 표시한)에 의해 표시된(나는, ≤)(위로)를에{\displaystyle(I,\leq)}는 직접적인 세트는 세트라[15]이것은 모두에게 나는, j∈이 전처{\displaystyle i,j\in 나는,}을 의미한다.ists일부 k∈ 나는{\displaystyle k\in 나는}가 나는 ≤ k와 j≤ k.{\displaystylei\leq k{\text{과}}j\leq k.}에게 어떤 지수 i와 j,{\displaystyle 나는{\text{과}}j,}기호 j≥ 나는{\displaystyle j\geq 나는}은 정의될 생각은 나는 ≤ j{\displaystyle i\leq j}는 동안 나는 <, j{\displaystyle i<, j.}나는s는 (를) 보유한다는 의미로 정의되었지만 i 만약 이(가) 대칭이라면 i 와 i leq j {\ j {{{}에

[15] 그물. 에 설정된 비어 있지 않은 상태의 지도입니다.

표기법과 정의 가정 이름
(, ) 지시된 집합이다. 에서 시작하는 I 의 꼬리 또는 섹션
=( ) { I 그물망이다. 에서 시작되는 의 꼬리 또는 단면
=( i) {\x_{\}=\}\in I}}}는 그물망이다. Set or prefilter of tails/sections of Also called the eventuality filter base generated by (the tails of) If is a sequence then 을(를) 대신 순차 필터 베이스라고 한다.[16]
=( i) {\x_{\}=\}\in I}}}는 그물망이다. (사건성) x (){\필터
:( , ) I 그물이다. 에서 시작하는 f 의 꼬리 또는 섹션

엄격한 비교 사용에 대한 경고

만약 x ∙)()나는)나는 나는 세트를}와 나는 ∈ 순 그 때 그것을 가능하다{\displaystyle i\in 나는})을{\displaystyle x_{\bullet}(x_{나는}\right)_{나는 i\in}, 나는{)j∈ 나는:나는입니다.;j와 j∈ 1세}, I~{\displaystyle x_{>나는}=\left\{x_{j}\in:~i&gt원;j{\text{과}}j\in I\right\},}은 c은 ∈는 분명 alled 이후x 일(예: i 이(가) 방향 I displaystyle I}의 상한인 경우).이 경우{> i: 은(는) 빈 세트가 포함되어 프리필터가 되지 못하게 된다(나중에 정의됨).{)≥ 나는: 난 ∈}{\displaystyle \left\{x_{\geq 나는}~로 테일즈 ⁡()∙)(\left(x_{\bullet}\right)}를 정의하는 이것은(중요한)이유:~i\in I\right\}}보다는{)>i: 난 ∈}{\displaystyle \left\{x_{>나는}~:~i\in I\right\}}또는{. )>나는:나는}나는 ∈ ∪{)≥ 나는: 난 ∈}{\displaystyle \left\{x_{>나는}~:~i\in I\right\}\cup \left\{x_{\geq 나는}~:~i\in I\right\}}와 그것도 이 이유에서 일반적으로 때, 그물의 꼬리의 prefilter를 다루는데 있어서 엄격한 불평등<>{\displaystyle \,<, \,}호환 inequali과 함께 사용할 못할 수도 있다.ty

필터 및 프리필터

다음은 제품군 이(가) 소유할 수 있는 속성 목록이며 필터, 프리필터 및 필터 하위베이스의 정의 속성을 형성한다.필요할 때마다 ( X). )라고 가정해야 한다

집합의 제품군은 다음과 같다.
  1. . {\mathcal 또는 otherwise , \varnot \mathcal { 경우 부적절하거나[17] 퇴보한다고 한다.
  2. , {(가) 있을 때마다 A\ B}이) 있는 아래로 향한다
    • This property can be characterized in terms of directedness, which explains the word "directed": A binary relation on is called (upward) directed if for any two there is some satisfying Using in place of gives the definition of directed downward whereas using instead gives the definition of directed upward.Explicitly, is directed downward (resp. directed upward) if and only if for all there exists some "greater" such that (resp. such that ) − where the "greater" element is always on the right hand side,[note 5] − which can be rewritten as (resp. as ).
    • 계열이 \},(예: {B {\in {\ {에 대해 가장 큰 요소를 가지고 있으면 반드시 아래로 향한다.
  3. 유한 교차점(resp) 아래 폐쇄됨.교차로(resp)인 경우 조합. 의 두 요소 중 조합)은 B. {\의 요소다.
    • (가) 유한 교차로에서 닫히면 B {이(가) 아래로 향한다.그 역은 대체로 거짓이다.
  4. 만약 B및 B=B↑ X,{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}℘(X)⊆ 상향 또는 동중 성자 원소 X에서{X\displaystyle}[6]\subseteq\wp(X){\text{과}}{{B\mathcal}}={{B\mathcal}}^{X\uparrow},}또는 동등하게, 만약 때마다 B∈ B{\displaystyle B\in{{B\mathcal}}}과 일부 세트 C{C\displaystyle} 앉아 마감했다.isfies Similarly, is downward closed if An upward (respectively, downward) closed set is also called상위 세트 또는 이체 세트(하위 세트 또는 하위 세트)
    • The family which is the upward closure of is the unique smallest (with respect to ) isotone family of sets over having {\을(를) 하위 집합으로.

"property" 및 "direction downward"와 같이 위아래로 정의된 의 속성 중 상당수는 , X에 의존하지 않으므로 용어를 사용할 때 X 집합에 대한 언급은 선택 사항이다.", 의 필터와 같은 ", displaystyle X에서 위쪽 닫힘과 관련된 정의는 X에 따라 달라지므로 컨텍스트에서 명확하지 않은 X X}을를)로 설정해야 한다.

계열 B {은(는) a(n):
  1. (가) 유한 조합에서 아래로 닫히고 닫힌 경우에 이상적이다[17][18].
  2. ∅{\ }이가) X 에서 위쪽으로 닫히고 유한 교차로에서도 닫힌 경우[19] X이중 이상적임.Equivalently, is a dual ideal if for all [10]
    • "dual"이라는 단어의 설명: B{\{\(는) 가족인 이중 (resp. 이상)이다
      의 이상(이중 이상)이다. 즉, 이중 이상은 "이상적 이중"을 의미한다.The family should not be confused with because these two sets are not equal in general; for instance, The dual of the dual is the original family, meaning The set belongs to the dual of if and only if [17]
  3. 필터 X에서{X\displaystyle}[19][8]X에서 만약 B{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}}은properdual 이상이다.℘(X)∖{∅}{\displaystyle \wp(X)\setminus){\varnothing)}의 유한 교차로 아래 위쪽과 닫혀 있{X\displaystyle}즉, X{X\displaystyle}에 대한 필터는non−empty 부분 집합}. 폐쇄in Equivalently, it is a prefilter that is upward closed in In words, a filter on is a family of sets over that (1) is not empty (or equivalently, it contains ), (2) is closed under finite intersections, (3) , X에서 위쪽으로 닫히고, (4) 빈 세트를 요소로 가지고 있지 않다.
    • 경고: 어떤 작가들, 특히 알제브리스트들은 이중 이상을 의미하기 위해 "필터"를 사용하고, 다른 작가들, 특히 토폴로지스트들은 적절한/비감속적인 이중 이상을 의미하기 위해 "필터"를 사용한다.[20]수학적 문학을 읽을 때 항상 '필터'가 어떻게 정의되는지 확인하는 것이 좋다.그러나 "초광필터", "프리필터", "필터 서브베이스"의 정의는 항상 비지연성을 요구한다.이 글은 비감소성이 필요했던 앙리 카르탄의 필터에 대한 원래 정의를 사용한다.
    • A dual filter on is a family whose dual is a filter on Equivalently, it is an ideal on that does not contain as an element.
    • 전원 세트 ( X) (는) X에서 가 아닌 유일한 이중 이상이다.위상에서의 "필터"의 정의에서 ( {\X)}을 제외하는 것은 "prime number" 에서1 {\ 1을 제외하는 것과 같은 이점이 있다: 많은 중요한 결과에서 "비-디제너제너레이션"(" 또는 "의 아날로그)을 지정할 필요가 없으므로, 결과적으로 maki가 된다.ng 그들의 진술이 덜 어색하다.
  4. }이가) 적절하고 아래쪽으로 향할 경우 프리필터 또는 필터 베이스[8][21].마찬가지로 의 위쪽 닫힘 이(가) 필터라면 프리필터라고 불린다.또한 일부 필터에 해당하는 모든 패밀리로 정의할 수 있다 참조).[9]A proper family is a prefilter if and only if [9] A family is a prefilter if and only if the same is true of its upward closure.
    • If is a prefilter then its upward closure is the unique smallest (relative to ) filter on containing and it is called the filter generated by A filter is said to be generated by a prefilter if in which is. 대한 필터 베이스를 호출함.
    • 필터와 달리 프리필터는 한정된 교차로에서 반드시 닫히지 않는다.
  5. π-system B }이가) 유한 교차로에서 폐쇄된 경우.비어 있지 않은 모든 B 은(는) , 이(는) 생성되는 π–system이라고 하는 고유한 가장 작은 π-system에 포함되어 있으며, 이 (. {\{\을(를) 포함하는 모든 ––systems의 교차점{\{\에서 집합의 가능한 모든 유한 교차점 집합의 집합과 동일함
    • π-시스템은 적절한 경우에만 프리필터다.모든 필터는 적절한 π-시스템이고 모든 적절한 π-시스템은 프리필터지만 대화 내용은 일반적으로 유지되지 않는다.
    • 프리필터는프리필터가 생성한 π-system과 동등하며 이러한 두 패밀리는 X. 에 동일한 필터를 생성한다.
  6. } 및 이(가) 다음과 같은 동등한 조건 중 하나를 충족하면 하위 베이스[8][22] 필터링하고 중심을 맞춘다[9].
    1. has the finite intersection property, which means that the intersection of any finite family of (one or more) sets in is not empty; explicitly, this means that whenever 그 다음 n.
    2. 에서 생성이 적절함, 즉 ∉( .{\
    3. 이(가) 생성한 π–시스템은 프리필터다.
    4. (는) 일부 프리필터의 하위 집합이다.
    5. (는) 일부 필터의 하위 집합이다.
    • 이(가) 필터 하위 베이스라고 가정하십시오.Then there is a unique smallest (relative to ) filter containing called the filter generated by , and 은(는) 이 필터의 필터 하위 베이스라고 한다.This filter is equal to the intersection of all filters on that are supersets of The π–system generated by denoted by will be a prefilter and a subset of Moreover, the filter generated by is equal to the upward closure of meaning {{B\mathcal}}.}[9]그러나, B↑ X)FB{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}^{X\uparrow}={{F\mathcal}}_{{B\mathcal}}}F에 만일 B{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}}은 prefilter(비록 B↑ X{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}^{X\uparrow}}은 항상 위쪽 문을 닫필터 subbase
    • 필터 하위 베이스 – 가장 작은 에 비해 가장 작은 프리필터는 특정 상황에서만 존재할 수 있다예를 들어 필터 하위 베이스 프리필터인 경우 이 값이 존재한다.It also exists if the filter (or equivalently, the π–system) generated by is principal, in which case is the unique smallest prefilter containing Otherwise, in general B {\을(를) 포함하는 가장 작은 프리필터가 없을 수 있음.For this reason, some authors may refer to the π–system generated by as the prefilter generated by However, as shown in an example below, if a –smallest prefilter does exist (say it is denoted by ) then contrary to usual expectations, it is not necessarily equal to "the prefilter generated by " (that is, is possible).And if the filter subbase happens to also be a prefilter but not a π-system then unfortunately, "the prefilter generated by this prefilter" (meaning ) will not be (that is, is possible even when is a prefilter), which is why this article will prefer the accurate and unambiguous terminology of "the π–system generated by ".
  7. B{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}}[17][23]의 Subfilter 필터 F의{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}}}과 F{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}}}은 superfilter 만약}\subseteq{{F\mathcal}B{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}}은 필터와 B⊆ F{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}}이 filte.개발,
    • 중요한 것은 "superfilter is a superfilter"라는 표현은 "superfilter is a filters of"의 아날로그 필터에 대한 것이다.그래서 공통적으로 "sub"라는 접두사를 가지고 있음에도 불구하고, "subfilter is a subfilter"는 사실 "subpilter is a subpilter"의 역순이다.However, can also be written which is described by saying " is subordinate to " With this terminology, "is subor"dinate to"는 필터(그리고 프리필터의 경우에도)의 아날로그인 " is serpendence of"[24]를 사용하게 되는데, 이는 "dinate"와 기호symbol 을(를) 사용하는 것이 도움이 될 수 있는 하나의 상황을 만든다.

= X또한 에 가치 있는 그물도 없음)에 대한 프리필터가 없기 때문에 대부분의 저자와 마찬가지로 이 글은 이 가정이 필요할 때마다 X을 자동으로 가정한다.

기본 예시

명명된 예제

  • X{X\displaystyle}에[25][11]그것은 독특한 최소한의 필터 X{X\displaystyle}에 모든 필터의 하위 집합 그 singleton}X에서 또는 사소한 밀착한 필터라고 불린다.{X\displaystyle}모든 prefilter 하지만, 그것일 필요는 없다 하위 집합에 B){X}{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}=\{X\}을 세웠다.x
  • 이중 이상적){\ {\[10]실제로 필터가 아님에도 불구하고)의 퇴행적 필터라고도 불린다. 에서 X. 의 필터가 아닌 유일한 이중 이상이다.
  • If is a topological space and then the neighborhood filter at is a filter on By definition, a family 이(가) 프리필터(resp)인 경우에만(, x 에서 subrony bases(. neighbase)라고 한다. 는) 필터 하위 기반이며, 이() 생성하는 X 의 필터는 주변 N x). )과 동일하다. 열린 동네의 하위 패밀리 ( ) N( ) N( ). )의 필터 베이스다 Both prefilters also form a bases for topologies on with the topology generated being coarser than This example immediately generalizes from neighb비어 있지 않은 하위 집합 X의 인접 지역에 대한 점의 변화
  • is an elementary prefilter[26] if for some sequence
  • 이(가) 일부 기본 프리필터에 의해 X 필터인 경우[27] 대한 기본 필터 또는 순차 필터로,결국 일정하지 않은 시퀀스에 의해 생성되는 꼬리의 필터는 반드시 초필터가 아니다.[28]카운트할 수 있는 세트의 모든 주 필터는 카운트할 수 있는 무한 세트의 모든 코피나이트 필터와 마찬가지로 순차적이다.[10]정밀하게 많은 순차 필터들의 교차점은 다시 순차적이다.[10]
  • 모든 코피나이트 하위 집합(X {\displaystyle 에서 보수가 유한한 집합) 중 F {F이(가) 무한( 하게 X {\ 경우에만)이 적절하며, 이 경우 가 무한하다.{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}}}은 필터에서 X{X\displaystyle}은 프레셰 필터 또는cofinite 필터에서 X.{X\displaystyle}[11][25]만약 X{X\displaystyle}은 유한한 다음 F{\displaystyle{{F\mathcal}}}와 이중 이상적인 ℘(X),{\displaystyle \wp(X),}이 아닌 filte.rIf is infinite then the family of complements of singleton sets is a filter subbase that generates the Fréchet filter on As with any family of sets over that contains X에 있는 Frechet 필터의 커널은 비어 있는 집합: F =.{\{\
  • The intersection of all elements in any non–empty family is itself a filter on called the infimum or greatest lower bound of which is why it may be denoted by Said differently, 의 모든 필터에는 이 부분 집합으로 포함되어 있기 때문에 이 교차로는 절대 비어 있지 않다.정의에 의해, 하한은finest/largest(그리고 ≤ ⊆에 비례하여{\displaystyle\,\subseteq \,{\text{과}}\,\leq\,})필터 F.{\displaystyle \mathbb{F}의 각 멤버에 대한 기본이 된다.}[11]만약 B형과 F{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}{\text{과}}{{F\mathcal}}}은 필터 그 다음에 그들의 i.nfi엄마 필터에(X){\displaystyle \operatorname{필터}(X)⁡}은 필터가 B(∪)F.{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}\,(\cup)\,{{F\mathcal}}.}[9]만약 B형과 F{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}{\text{과}}{{F\mathcal}}}은 prefilters 그 다음에 B(∪)F{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}\,(\cup).
    • is a prefilter that is coarser (with respect to ) than both (that is,
    • ); indeed, it is one of the finest such prefilters, meaning that if is a prefilter such that
    {F}}}그때 반드시 S≤ B(∪)F.{\displaystyle{{S\mathcal}}\leq{{B\mathcal}}\,(\cup)\,{{F\mathcal}}.}[9]더 일반적으로, 만약 B형과 F{\displaystyle{{B\mathcal}}{\text{과}}{{F\mathcal}}}은non−empty 가족들과 S다음과 같은 경우={SB와 S≤ F≤℘(X):S⊆}.
    • then and
    • . 에 대한 가장요소(S \
  • Let and let The supremum or least upper bound of denoted by is the smallest (relative to ) dual ideal on containing every element of 부분 집합으로 }. 즉, 부분 으로F {\\을(를) 하는X {\ X에서 가장 작은 이상이다.This dual ideal is where is the π–system generated by As with any non–empty family of sets, is contained in some filter on if and only if it is a filter subbase, or equivalently, if and only if is a filter on in which case this family is the smallest{\\에 대한 F {\ \ {의 모든 요소를 하위 집합으로 포함하고 반드시 F ( ). )에 대한 필터
  • Let and let The supremum or least upper bound of denoted by if it exists, is by definition the smallest (relative to ) filter on containing every element of as a subset. If it exists then necessarily [11] (as defined above) and will also be equal to the intersection of all filters on containing This supremum of exists if and only if the dual ideal is a filter on The least upper bound of a family of filters may fail to be a filter.[11] Indeed, if contains at least 2 distinct elements then there exist filters for which there does not exist a filter that contains both If is not a filter subbase then the supremum of does not exist and the same is true of its supremum in but their supremum in the set of all dual ideals on will exist (it being the degenerate filter ).[10]
    • If are prefilters (resp. filters on ) then is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if it is non–degenerate (or said differently, if and only if mesh), in which case it is one of the coarsest prefilters (resp. the coarsest filter) on (with respect to ) that is finer (with respect to ) than both this means that if is any prefilter (resp. any filter) such that then necessarily [9] in which case it is denoted by [10]
  • Let be non−empty sets and for every let be a dual ideal on If is any dual ideal on then is a dual ideal on called Kowalsky's dual ideal or Kowalsky's filter.[17]

Other examples

  • Let and let which makes a prefilter and a filter subbase that is not closed under finite intersections. Because is a prefilter, the smallest prefilter containing is The π–system generated by is In particular, the smallest prefilter containing the filter subbase is not equal to the set of all finite intersections of sets in The filter on generated by is All three of the π–system generates, and are examples of fixed, principal, ultra prefilters that are principal at the point is also an ultrafilter on
  • Let be a topological space, and define where is necessarily finer than [29] If is non–empty (resp. non–degenerate, a filter subbase, a prefilter, closed under finite unions) then the same is true of If is a filter on then is a prefilter but not necessarily a filter on although is a filter on equivalent to
  • The set of all dense open subsets of a (non–empty) topological space is a proper π–system and so also a prefilter. If (with ) then the set of all such that has finite Lebesgue measure is a proper π–system and prefilter that is also a proper subset of The prefilters generate the same filter on
  • A filter subbase with no smallest prefilter containing it: In general, if a filter subbase is not a π–system then an intersection of sets from will usually require a description involving variables that cannot be reduced down to only two (consider, for instance when ). This example illustrates an atypical class of a filter subbases where all sets in both and its generated π–system can be described as sets of the form so that in particular, no more than two variables (specifically, ) are needed to describe the generated π–system. For all let
    where always holds so no generality is lost by adding the assumption For all real if is non-negative then [note 6] For every set of positive reals, let[note 7]
    Let and suppose is not a singleton set. Then is a filter subbase but not a prefilter and is the π–system it generates, so that is the unique smallest filter in containing However, is not a filter on (nor is it a prefilter because it is not directed downward, although it is a filter subbase) and is a proper subset of the filter If are non−empty intervals then the filter subbases generate the same filter on if and only if If is a prefilter satisfying [note 8] then for any the family is also a prefilter satisfying This shows that there cannot exist a minimal/least (with respect to ) prefilter that both contains and is a subset of the π–system generated by This remains true even if the requirement that the prefilter be a subset of is removed; that is, (in sharp contrast to filters) there does not exist a minimal/least (with respect to ) prefilter containing the filter subbase

Ultrafilters

There are many other characterizations of "ultrafilter" and "ultra prefilter," which are listed in the article on ultrafilters. Important properties of ultrafilters are also described in that article.

A non–empty family of sets is/is an:
  1. Ultra[8][30] if and any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
    1. For every set there exists some set such that (or equivalently, such that ).
    2. For every set there exists some set such that
      • This characterization of " is ultra" does not depend on the set so mentioning the set is optional when using the term "ultra."
    3. For every set (not necessarily even a subset of ) there exists some set such that
      • If satisfies this condition then so does every superset For example, if is any singleton set then is ultra and consequently, any non–degenerate superset of (such as its upward closure) is also ultra.
  2. Ultra prefilter[8][30] if it is a prefilter that is also ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra. A prefilter is ultra if and only if it satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
    1. is maximal in with respect to which means that
      • Although this statement is identical to that given below for ultrafilters, here is merely assumed to be a prefilter; it need not be a filter.
    2. is ultra (and thus an ultrafilter).
    3. is equivalent (with respect to ) to some ultrafilter.
    • A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter. A filter subbase is ultra if and only if it is a maximal filter subbase with respect to (as above).[17]
  3. Ultrafilter on [8][30] if it is a filter on that is ultra. Equivalently, an ultrafilter on is a filter that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
    1. is generated by an ultra prefilter.
    2. For any [17]
    3. This condition can be restated as: is partitioned by and its dual
      • The sets are disjoint whenever is a prefilter.
    4. is an ideal.[17]
    5. For any if then
    6. For any if then (a filter with this property is called a prime filter).
      • This property extends to any finite union of two or more sets.
    7. For any if then either
    8. is a maximal filter on ; meaning that if is a filter on such that then necessarily (this equality may be replaced by ).
      • If is upward closed then So this characterization of ultrafilters as maximal filters can be restated as:
      • Because subordination is for filters the analog of "is a subnet/subsequence of" (specifically, "subnet" should mean "AA–subnet," which is defined below), this characterization of an ultrafilter as being a "maximally subordinate filter" suggests that an ultrafilter can be interpreted as being analogous to some sort of "maximally deep net" (which could, for instance, mean that "when viewed only from " in some sense, it is indistinguishable from its subnets, as is the case with any net valued in a singleton set for example),[note 9] which is an idea that is actually made rigorous by ultranets. The ultrafilter lemma is then the statement that every filter ("net") has some subordinate filter ("subnet") that is "maximally subordinate" ("maximally deep").

Any non–degenerate family that has a singleton set as an element is ultra, in which case it will then be an ultra prefilter if and only if it also has the finite intersection property. The trivial filter is ultra if and only if is a singleton set.

The ultrafilter lemma

The following important theorem is due to Alfred Tarski (1930).[31]

The ultrafilter lemma/principal/theorem[11] (Tarski)Every filter on a set is a subset of some ultrafilter on

A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.[11][proof 1] Assuming the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel (ZF), the ultrafilter lemma follows from the Axiom of choice (in particular from Zorn's lemma) but is strictly weaker than it. The ultrafilter lemma implies the Axiom of choice for finite sets. If only dealing with Hausdorff spaces, then most basic results (as encountered in introductory courses) in Topology (such as Tychonoff's theorem for compact Hausdorff spaces and the Alexander subbase theorem) and in functional analysis (such as the Hahn–Banach theorem) can be proven using only the ultrafilter lemma; the full strength of the axiom of choice might not be needed.

Kernels

The kernel is useful in classifying properties of prefilters and other families of sets.

The kernel[6] of a family of sets is the intersection of all sets that are elements of

If then for any point

Properties of kernels

If then and this set is also equal to the kernel of the π–system that is generated by In particular, if is a filter subbase then the kernels of all of the following sets are equal:

(1) (2) the π–system generated by and (3) the filter generated by

If is a map then If while if are equivalent then If are principal then they are equivalent if and only if

Classifying families by their kernels
A family of sets is/is an:
  1. Free[7] if or equivalently, if this can be restated as
    • A filter is free if and only if is infinite and contains the Fréchet filter on as a subset.
  2. Fixed if in which case, is said to be fixed by any point
    • Any fixed family is necessarily a filter subbase.
  3. Principal[7] if
    • A proper principal family of sets is necessarily a prefilter.
  4. Discrete or Principal at[25] if
    • The principal filter at is the filter A filter is principal at if and only if
  5. Countably deep if whenever is a countable subset then [10]

If is a principal filter on then and

where is also the smallest prefilter that generates

Family of examples: For any non–empty the family is free but it is a filter subbase if and only if no finite union of the form covers in which case the filter that it generates will also be free. In particular, is a filter subbase if is countable (for example, the primes), a meager set in a set of finite measure, or a bounded subset of If is a singleton set then is a subbase for the Fréchet filter on

For every filter there exists a unique pair of dual ideals such that is free, is principal, and and do not mesh (that is, ). The dual ideal is called the free part of while is called the principal part[10] where at least one of these dual ideals is filter. If is principal then otherwise, and is a free (non–degenerate) filter.[10]

Finite prefilters and finite sets

If a filter subbase is finite then it is fixed (that is, not free); this is because is a finite intersection and the filter subbase has the finite intersection property. A finite prefilter is necessarily principal, although it does not have to be closed under finite intersections.

If is finite then all of the conclusions above hold for any In particular, on a finite set there are no free filter subbases (and so no free prefilters), all prefilters are principal, and all filters on are principal filters generated by their (non–empty) kernels.

The trivial filter is always a finite filter on and if is infinite then it is the only finite filter because a non–trivial finite filter on a set is possible if and only if is finite. However, on any infinite set there are non–trivial filter subbases and prefilters that are finite (although they cannot be filters). If is a singleton set then the trivial filter is the only proper subset of and moreover, this set is a principal ultra prefilter and any superset (where ) with the finite intersection property will also be a principal ultra prefilter (even if is infinite).

Characterizing fixed ultra prefilters

If a family of sets is fixed (that is, ) then is ultra if and only if some element of is a singleton set, in which case will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter is ultra if and only if is a singleton set.

Every filter on that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on other than these.[7]

The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point.

PropositionIf is an ultrafilter on then the following are equivalent:

  1. is fixed, or equivalently, not free, meaning
  2. is principal, meaning
  3. Some element of is a finite set.
  4. Some element of is a singleton set.
  5. is principal at some point of which means
  6. does not contain the Fréchet filter on
  7. is sequential.[10]

Finer/coarser, subordination, and meshing

The preorder that is defined below is of fundamental importance for the use of prefilters (and filters) in topology. For instance, this preorder is used to define the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence",[24] where "" can be interpreted as " is a subsequence of " (so "subordinate to" is the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence of"). It is also used to define prefilter convergence in a topological space. The definition of meshes with which is closely related to the preorder is used in Topology to define cluster points.

Two families of sets mesh[8] and are compatible, indicated by writing if If do not mesh then they are dissociated. If then are said to mesh if mesh, or equivalently, if the trace of which is the family

does not contain the empty set, where the trace is also called the restriction of

Declare that stated as is coarser than and is finer than (or subordinate to) [11][12][13][9][10] if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
  1. Definition: Every contains some Explicitly, this means that for every there is some such that
    • Said more briefly in plain English, if every set in is larger than some set in Here, a "larger set" means a superset.
    • In words, states exactly that is larger than some set in The equivalence of (a) and (b) follows immediately.
    • From this characterization, it follows that if are families of sets, then
  2. which is equivalent to ;
  3. ;
  4. which is equivalent to ;

and if in addition is upward closed, which means that then this list can be extended to include:

  1. [6]
    • So in this case, this definition of " is finer than " would be identical to the topological definition of "finer" had been topologies on

If an upward closed family is finer than (that is, ) but then is said to be strictly finer than and is strictly coarser than

Two families are comparable if one of these sets is finer than the other.[11]

For example, if is any family then always holds and furthermore,

Assume that are families of sets that satisfy Then and and also If in addition to is a filter subbase and then is a filter subbase[9] and also mesh.[19][proof 2] More generally, if both and if the intersection of any two elements of is non–empty, then mesh.[proof 2] Every filter subbase is coarser than both the π–system that it generates and the filter that it generates.[9]

If are families such that the family is ultra, and then is necessarily ultra. It follows that any family that is equivalent to an ultra family will necessarily be ultra. In particular, if is a prefilter then either both and the filter it generates are ultra or neither one is ultra. If a filter subbase is ultra then it is necessarily a prefilter, in which case the filter that it generates will also be ultra. A filter subbase that is not a prefilter cannot be ultra; but it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter and filter generated by to be ultra. If is upward closed in then [10]

Relational properties of subordination

The relation is reflexive and transitive, which makes it into a preorder on [32]

Symmetry: For any So the set has more than one point if and only if the relation is not symmetric.

Antisymmetry: If but while the converse does not hold in general, it does hold if is upward closed (such as if is a filter). Two filters are equivalent if and only if they are equal, which makes the restriction of to antisymmetric. But in general, is not antisymmetric on nor on ; that is, does not necessarily imply ; not even if both are prefilters.[13] For instance, if is a prefilter but not a filter then

Equivalent families of sets

The preorder induces its canonical equivalence relation on where for all is equivalent to if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:[9][6]

  1. The upward closures of are equal.

Two upward closed (in ) subsets of are equivalent if and only if they are equal.[9] If then necessarily and is equivalent to Every equivalence class other than contains a unique representative (that is, element of the equivalence class) that is upward closed in [9]

Properties preserved between equivalent families

Let be arbitrary and let be any family of sets. If are equivalent (which implies that ) then for each of the statements/properties listed below, either it is true of both or else it is false of both :[32]

  1. Not empty
  2. Proper (that is, is not an element)
    • Moreover, any two degenerate families are necessarily equivalent.
  3. Filter subbase
  4. Prefilter
    • In which case generate the same filter on (that is, their upward closures in are equal).
  5. Free
  6. Principal
  7. Ultra
  8. Is equal to the trivial filter
    • In words, this means that the only subset of that is equivalent to the trivial filter is the trivial filter. In general, this conclusion of equality does not extend to non−trivial filters (one exception is when both families are filters).
  9. Meshes with
  10. Is finer than
  11. Is coarser than
  12. Is equivalent to

Missing from the above list is the word "filter" because this property is not preserved by equivalence. However, if are filters on then they are equivalent if and only if they are equal; this characterization does not extend to prefilters.

Equivalence of prefilters and filter subbases

If is a prefilter on then the following families are always equivalent to each other:

  1. ;
  2. the π–system generated by ;
  3. the filter on generated by ;

and moreover, these three families all generate the same filter on (that is, the upward closures in of these families are equal).

In particular, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates. By transitivity, two prefilters are equivalent if and only if they generate the same filter.[9][proof 3] Every prefilter is equivalent to exactly one filter on which is the filter that it generates (that is, the prefilter's upward closure). Said differently, every equivalence class of prefilters contains exactly one representative that is a filter. In this way, filters can be considered as just being distinguished elements of these equivalence classes of prefilters.[9]

A filter subbase that is not also a prefilter cannot be equivalent to the prefilter (or filter) that it generates. In contrast, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates. This is why prefilters can, by and large, be used interchangeably with the filters that they generate while filter subbases cannot. Every filter is both a π–system and a ring of sets.

Examples of determining equivalence/non–equivalence

Examples: Let and let be the set of integers (or the set ). Define the sets

All three sets are filter subbases but none are filters on and only is prefilter (in fact, is even free and closed under finite intersections). The set is fixed while is free (unless ). They satisfy but no two of these families are equivalent; moreover, no two of the filters generated by these three filter subbases are equivalent/equal. This conclusion can be reached by showing that the π–systems that they generate are not equivalent. Unlike with every set in the π–system generated by contains as a subset,[note 10] which is what prevents their generated π–systems (and hence their generated filters) from being equivalent. If was instead then all three families would be free and although the sets would remain not equivalent to each other, their generated π–systems would be equivalent and consequently, they would generate the same filter on ; however, this common filter would still be strictly coarser than the filter generated by

Set theoretic properties and constructions relevant to topology

Trace and meshing

If is a prefilter (resp. filter) on then the trace of which is the family is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if mesh (that is, [11]), in which case the trace of is said to be induced by . If is ultra and if mesh then the trace is ultra. If is an ultrafilter on then the trace of is a filter on if and only if

For example, suppose that is a filter on is such that Then mesh and generates a filter on that is strictly finer than [11]

When prefilters mesh

Given non–empty families the family

satisfies and If is proper (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase) then this is also true of both In order to make any meaningful deductions about from needs to be proper (that is, which is the motivation for the definition of "mesh". In this case, is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase) if and only if this is true of both Said differently, if are prefilters then they mesh if and only if is a prefilter. Generalizing gives a well known characterization of "mesh" entirely in terms of subordination (that is, ):

Two prefilters (resp. filter subbases) mesh if and only if there exists a prefilter (resp. filter subbase) such that and

If the least upper bound of two filters exists in then this least upper bound is equal to [28]

Images and preimages under functions

Throughout, will be maps between non–empty sets.

Images of prefilters

Let Many of the properties that may have are preserved under images of maps; notable exceptions include being upward closed, being closed under finite intersections, and being a filter, which are not necessarily preserved.

Explicitly, if one of the following properties is true of then it will necessarily also be true of (although possibly not on the codomain unless is surjective):[11][14][33][34][35][31]

  • Filter properties: ultra, ultrafilter, filter, prefilter, filter subbase, dual ideal, upward closed, proper/non–degenerate.
  • Ideal properties: ideal, closed under finite unions, downward closed, directed upward.

Moreover, if is a prefilter then so are both [11] The image under a map of an ultra set is again ultra and if is an ultra prefilter then so is

If is a filter then is a filter on the range but it is a filter on the codomain if and only if is surjective.[33] Otherwise it is just a prefilter on and its upward closure must be taken in to obtain a filter. The upward closure of is

where if is upward closed in (that is, a filter) then this simplifies to:

If then taking to be the inclusion map shows that any prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on is also a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on [11]

Preimages of prefilters

Let Under the assumption that is surjective:

is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, π–system, closed under finite unions, proper) if and only if this is true of

However, if is an ultrafilter on then even if is surjective (which would make a prefilter), it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter to be neither ultra nor a filter on [34] (see this[note 11] footnote for an example).

If is not surjective then denote the trace of by where in this case particular case the trace satisfies:

and consequently also:

This last equality and the fact that the trace is a family of sets over means that to draw conclusions about the trace can be used in place of and the surjection can be used in place of For example:[14][11][35]

is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, π–system, proper) if and only if this is true of

In this way, the case where is not (necessarily) surjective can be reduced down to the case of a surjective function (which is a case that was described at the start of this subsection).

Even if is an ultrafilter on if is not surjective then it is nevertheless possible that which would make degenerate as well. The next characterization shows that degeneracy is the only obstacle. If is a prefilter then the following are equivalent:[14][11][35]

  1. is a prefilter;
  2. is a prefilter;
  3. ;
  4. meshes with

and moreover, if is a prefilter then so is [14][11]

If and if denotes the inclusion map then the trace of is equal to [11] This observation allows the results in this subsection to be applied to investigating the trace on a set.

Bijections, injections, and surjections

All properties involving filters are preserved under bijections. This means that if is a bijection, then is a prefilter (resp. ultra, ultra prefilter, filter on ultrafilter on filter subbase, π–system, ideal on etc.) if and only if the same is true of [34]

A map is injective if and only if for all prefilters is equivalent to [28] The image of an ultra family of sets under an injection is again ultra.

The map is a surjection if and only if whenever is a prefilter on then the same is true of (this result does not require the ultrafilter lemma).

Subordination is preserved by images and preimages

The relation is preserved under both images and preimages of families of sets.[11] This means that for any families [35]

Moreover, the following relations always hold for any family of sets :[35]

where equality will hold if is surjective.[35] Furthermore,

If then[10]

and [35] where equality will hold if is injective.[35]

Products of prefilters

Suppose is a family of one or more non–empty sets, whose product will be denoted by and for every index let

denote the canonical projection. Let be non−empty families, also indexed by such that for each The product of the families [11] is defined identically to how the basic open subsets of the product topology are defined (had all of these been topologies). That is, both the notations
denote the family of all subsets such that for all but finitely many and where for any one of these finitely many exceptions (that is, for any such that necessarily ). When every is a filter subbase then the family is a filter subbase for the filter on generated by [11] If is a filter subbase then the filter on that it generates is called the filter generated by .[11] If every is a prefilter on then will be a prefilter on and moreover, this prefilter is equal to the coarsest prefilter such that for every [11] However, may fail to be a filter on even if every is a filter on [11]

Set subtraction and some examples

Set subtracting away a subset of the kernel

If is a prefilter on then is a prefilter, where this latter set is a filter if and only if is a filter and In particular, if is a neighborhood basis at a point in a topological space having at least 2 points, then is a prefilter on This construction is used to define in terms of prefilter convergence.

Using duality between ideals and dual ideals

There is a dual relation or which is defined to mean that every is contained in some Explicitly, this means that for every , there is some such that This relation is dual to in sense that if and only if [6] The relation is closely related to the downward closure of a family in a manner similar to how is related to the upward closure family.

For an example that uses this duality, suppose is a map and Define

which contains the empty set if and only if does. It is possible for to be an ultrafilter and for to be empty or not closed under finite intersections (see footnote for example).[note 12] Although does not preserve properties of filters very well, if is downward closed (resp. closed under finite unions, an ideal) then this will also be true for Using the duality between ideals and dual ideals allows for a construction of the following filter.

Suppose is a filter on and let be its dual in If then 's dual will be a filter.

Other topology related examples

Example: The set of all dense open subsets of a topological space is a proper π–system and a prefilter. If the space is a Baire space, then the set of all countable intersections of dense open subsets is a π–system and a prefilter that is finer than

Example: The family of all dense open sets of having finite Lebesgue measure is a proper π–system and a free prefilter. The prefilter is properly contained in, and not equivalent to, the prefilter consisting of all dense open subsets of Since is a Baire space, every countable intersection of sets in is dense in (and also comeagre and non–meager) so the set of all countable intersections of elements of is a prefilter and π–system; it is also finer than, and not equivalent to,

Convergence, limits, and cluster points

Throughout, is a topological space.

Prefilters vs. filters

With respect to maps and subsets, the property of being a prefilter is in general more well behaved and better preserved than the property of being a filter. For instance, the image of a prefilter under some map is again a prefilter; but the image of a filter under a non–surjective map is never a filter on the codomain, although it will be a prefilter. The situation is the same with preimages under non–injective maps (even if the map is surjective). If is a proper subset then any filter on will not be a filter on although it will be a prefilter.

One advantage that filters have is that they are distinguished representatives of their equivalence class (relative to ), meaning that any equivalence class of prefilters contains a unique filter. This property may be useful when dealing with equivalence classes of prefilters (for instance, they are useful in the construction of completions of uniform spaces via Cauchy filters). The many properties that characterize ultrafilters are also often useful. They are used to, for example, construct the Stone–Čech compactification. The use of ultrafilters generally requires that the ultrafilter lemma be assumed. But in the many fields where the axiom of choice (or the Hahn–Banach theorem) is assumed, the ultrafilter lemma necessarily holds and does not require an addition assumption.

A note on intuition

Suppose that is a non–principal filter on an infinite set has one "upward" property (that of being closed upward) and one "downward" property (that of being directed downward). Starting with any there always exists some that is a proper subset of ; this may be continued ad infinitum to get a sequence of sets in with each being a proper subset of The same is not true going "upward", for if then there is no set in that contains as a proper subset. Thus when it comes to limiting behavior (which is a topic central to the field of topology), going "upward" leads to a dead end, while going "downward" is typically fruitful. So to gain understanding and intuition about how filters (and prefilter) relate to concepts in topology, the "downward" property is usually the one to concentrate on. This is also why so many topological properties can be described by using only prefilters, rather than requiring filters (which only differ from prefilters in that they are also upward closed). The "upward" property of filters is less important for topological intuition but it is sometimes useful to have for technical reasons. For example, with respect to every filter subbase is contained in a unique smallest filter but there may not exist a unique smallest prefilter containing it.

Limits and convergence

The following well known definition will be generalized to prefilters. A point is called a limit point, cluster point, or accumulation point of a subset if every neighborhood of contains a point of different from or equivalently, if The set of all limit points of is called the derived set of The closure of a set is equal to the union of together with the set of all limit points of

A family is said to converge in to a point or subset of [8] written [29] if in which case is said to be a limit (or if is a point, also limit point)[36] of Denote[8] the set of all these limit points by As usual, is defined to mean that and is the only limit point of that is, if also [29] (If the notation "" did not also require that the limit point be unique then the equals sign = would no longer be guaranteed to be transitive).

In words, converges to a point if and only if is finer than the neighborhood filter at that point. Explicitly, means that every neighborhood contains some as a subset (that is, ); thus the following then holds:

In the above definitions, it suffices to check that is finer than some (or equivalently, finer than every) neighborhood base in of the point or set (for example, such as or ). If then because if then Because is an open set, a family converges to if and only if so in particular, no filter or other non-degenerate family can converge to the empty set, which is why when dealing with convergent prefilters (or filter subbases), it is typically assumed (often without mention) that

Given the following are equivalent for a prefilter

  1. converges to
  2. converges to the set
  3. converges to
  4. There exists a family equivalent to that converges to

If is a prefilter and then converges to a point (or subset) of if and only if this is true of the trace [37] If is a filter subbase that converges to then this is also true of the filter that it generates (and also of any prefilter equivalent to this filter, such as the π-system generated by ).

Because subordination is transitive, if and moreover, for every both and the maximal/ultrafilter converge to Thus every topological space induces a canonical convergence defined by At the other extreme, the neighborhood filter is the smallest (that is, coarsest) filter on that converges to that is, any filter converging to must contain as a subset. Said differently, the family of filters that converge to consists exactly of those filter on that contain as a subset. Consequently, the finer the topology on then the fewer prefilters exist that have any limit points in

Cluster points

Say that is a cluster point or an accumulation point of a family [8] if meshes with the neighborhood filter at ; that is, if The set of all cluster points of is denoted by

Explicitly, this means that and every neighborhood of When is a prefilter then the definition of " mesh" can be characterized entirely in terms of the preorder

More generally, given say that

clusters at if meshes with the neighborhood filter of ; that is, if

In the above definitions, it suffices to check that meshes with some (or equivalently, meshes with every) neighborhood base in of Two equivalent families of sets have the exact same limit points and also the same cluster points. No matter the topology, for every both and the principal ultrafilter cluster at For any if clusters at some then clusters at No family clusters at and if

Given the following are equivalent for a prefilter :

  1. clusters at
  2. clusters at the set
  3. The family generated by clusters at
  4. There exists a family equivalent to that clusters at
  5. for every neighborhood of
    • If is a filter on then for every neighborhood
  6. There exists a prefilter subordinate to (that is, ) such that
    • This is the filter equivalent of " is a cluster point of a sequence if and only if there exists a subsequence converging to
    • In particular, if is a cluster point of a prefilter then is a prefilter subordinate to that converges to

If is an ultra prefilter on then is a cluster point of [30]

The set of all cluster points of a prefilter satisfies

which in particular shows that the set of all cluster points of any prefilter is a closed subset of [38][8] This also justifies the notation for the set of cluster points.[8]

Properties and relationships

Just like sequences and nets, it is possible for a prefilter on a topological space of infinite cardinality to not have any cluster points or limit points.[38]

If is a limit point of then is necessarily a limit point of any family finer than (that is, if then ).[38] In contrast, if is a cluster point of then is necessarily a cluster point of any family coarser than (that is, if mesh and then mesh).

Equivalent families and subordination

Any two equivalent families can be used interchangeably in the definitions of "limit of" and "cluster at" because their equivalency guarantees that if and only if and also that if and only if In essence, the preorder is incapable of distinguishing between equivalent families. Given two prefilters, whether or not they mesh can be characterized entirely in terms of subordination. Thus the two most fundamental concepts related to (pre)filters to Topology (that is, limit and cluster points) can both be defined entirely in terms of the subordination relation. This is why the preorder is of such great importance in applying (pre)filters to Topology.

Limit and cluster point relationships and sufficient conditions

Every limit point of a prefilter is also a cluster point of since if is a limit point of a prefilter then mesh,[19][38] which makes a cluster point of [8] Every accumulation point of an ultrafilter is also a limit point.

If is a filter subbase such that then In particular, any limit point of a filter subbase subordinate to is necessarily also a cluster point of If is a cluster point of a prefilter then is a prefilter subordinate to that converges to

If and if is a prefilter on then every cluster point of belongs to and any point in is a limit point of a filter on [38]

Primitive sets

A subset is called primitive[39] if it is the set of limit points of some ultrafilter on That is, if there exists an ultrafilter such that is equal to which recall denotes the set of limit points of

Any closed singleton subset of is a primitive subset of [39] The image of a primitive subset of under a continuous map is contained in a primitive subset of [39]

Assume that are two primitive subset of If is an open subset of such that then for any ultrafilter such that [39] In addition, if are distinct then there exists some and some ultrafilters such that and [39]

Other results

If is a complete lattice then:[citation needed]

  • The limit inferior of is the infimum of the set of all cluster points of
  • The limit superior of is the supremum of the set of all cluster points of
  • is a convergent prefilter if and only if its limit inferior and limit superior agree; in this case, the value on which they agree is the limit of the prefilter.

Limits of functions defined as limits of prefilters

If is a map from a set into a topological space then is called a limit point or limit (respectively, a cluster point) of with respect to [38] if is a limit point (resp. a cluster point) of in which case this may be expressed by writing If the limit is unique then the arrow may be replaced with an equals sign [29]

Explicitly, is a limit of with respect to if and only if

The definition of a convergent net is a special case of the above definition of a limit of a function. Specifically, if is a net then

where the left hand side states that is a limit of the net while the right hand side states that is a limit of the function with respect to (as defined above).

The table below shows how various types of limits encountered in analysis and topology can be defined in terms of the convergence of images (under ) of particular prefilters on the domain This shows that prefilters provide a general framework into which many of the various definitions of limits fit.[37] The limits in the left–most column are defined in their usual way with their obvious definitions.

Throughout, let be a map between topological spaces, If is Hausdorff then all arrows "" in the table may be replaced with equal signs "" and "" may be replaced with "".[29]

Type of limit if and only if Definition in terms of prefilters[37] Assumptions

or
is a sequence in
for a double-ended sequence
a seminormed space; for example, a Banach space

By defining different prefilters, many other notions of limits can be defined; for example,

Limits of that diverge to infinity can be defined by using the prefilters

For example, if and then can be defined to mean that holds and similarly, can be defined to mean If is valued in (or some other seminormed vector space) then if and only if holds.

Filters and nets

This article will describe the relationships between prefilters and nets in great detail so as to make it easier to understand later why subnets (with their most commonly used definitions) are not generally equivalent with "sub–prefilters".

Nets to prefilters

In the definitions below, the first statement is the standard definition of a limit point of a net (resp. a cluster point of a net) and it is gradually reworded until the corresponding filter concept is reached.

A net is said to converge in to a point written and is called a limit or limit point of [40] if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
  1. Definition: For every there exists some such that if
  2. For every there exists some such that the tail of starting at is contained in (that is, such that ).
  3. For every there exists some such that
  4. that is, the prefilter converges to
As usual, is defined to mean that and is the only limit point of that is, if also [40]
A point is called a cluster point or an accumulation point of a net if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
  1. Definition: For every and every there exists some such that
  2. For every and every the tail of starting at intersects
  3. For every and every
  4. mesh (by definition of "mesh").
  5. is a cluster point of
  6. For every neighborhood of there exists a subnet of that converges to [citation needed]

If is a map and is a net in then [4]

Prefilters to nets

A pointed set is a pair consisting of a non–empty set and an element For any family let

Define a canonical preorder on pointed sets by declaring

If even if so this preorder is not antisymmetric and given any family of sets is partially ordered if and only if consists entirely of singleton sets. If is a maximal element of ; moreover, all maximal elements are of this form. If is a greatest element if and only if in which case is the set of all greatest elements. However, a greatest element is a maximal element if and only if so there is at most one element that is both maximal and greatest. There is a canonical map defined by If then the tail of the assignment starting at is

Although is not, in general, a partially ordered set, it is a directed set if (and only if) is a prefilter. So the most immediate choice for the definition of "the net in induced by a prefilter " is the assignment from into

If is a prefilter on then the net associated with is the map

that is,

If is a prefilter on is a net in and the prefilter associated with is ; that is:[note 13]

This would not necessarily be true had been defined on a proper subset of For example, suppose has at least two distinct elements, is the indiscrete filter, and is arbitrary. Had instead been defined on the singleton set where the restriction of to will temporarily be denote by then the prefilter of tails associated with would be the principal prefilter rather than the original filter ; this means that the equality is false, so unlike the prefilter can not be recovered from Worse still, while is the unique minimal filter on the prefilter instead generates a maximal filter (that is, an ultrafilter) on

However, if is a net in then it is not in general true that is equal to because, for example, the domain of may be of a completely different cardinality than that of (since unlike the domain of the domain of an arbitrary net in could have any cardinality).

PropositionIf is a prefilter on and then

  1. is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of
Proof

Recall that and that if is a net in then (1) and (2) is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of By using it follows that

It also follows that is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of

Ultranets and ultra prefilters

A net is called an ultranet or universal net in if for every subset is eventually in or it is eventually in ; this happens if and only if is an ultra prefilter. A prefilter is an ultra prefilter if and only if is an ultranet in

Partially ordered net

The domain of the canonical net is in general not partially ordered. However, in 1955 Bruns and Schmidt discovered[41] a construction that allows for the canonical net to have a domain that is both partially ordered and directed; this was independently rediscovered by Albert Wilansky in 1970.[4] It begins with the construction of a strict partial order (meaning a transitive and irreflexive relation) on a subset of that is similar to the lexicographical order on of the strict partial orders For any in declare that if and only if

or equivalently, if and only if

The non−strict partial order associated with denoted by is defined by declaring that Unwinding these definitions gives the following characterization:

if and only if and also

which shows that is just the lexicographical order on induced by where is partially ordered by equality [note 14] Both are serial and neither possesses a greatest element or a maximal element; this remains true if they are each restricted to the subset of defined by

where it will henceforth be assumed that they are. Denote the assignment from this subset by:
If then just as with before, the tail of the starting at is equal to If is a prefilter on then is a net in whose domain is a partially ordered set and moreover, [4] Because the tails of are identical (since both are equal to the prefilter ), there is typically nothing lost by assuming that the domain of the net associated with a prefilter is both directed and partially ordered.[4] If the set is replaced with the positive rational numbers then the strict partial order will also be a dense order.

Subordinate filters and subnets

The notion of " is subordinate to " (written ) is for filters and prefilters what " is a subsequence of " is for sequences.[24] For example, if denotes the set of tails of and if denotes the set of tails of the subsequence (where ) then (that is, ) is true but is in general false. If is a net in a topological space and if is the neighborhood filter at a point then

Subordination analogs of results involving subsequences

The following results are the prefilter analogs of statements involving subsequences.[42] The condition "" which is also written is the analog of " is a subsequence of " So "finer than" and "subordinate to" is the prefilter analog of "subsequence of." Some people prefer saying "subordinate to" instead of "finer than" because it is more reminiscent of "subsequence of."

Proposition[42][38]Let be a prefilter on and let

  1. Suppose is a prefilter such that
    1. If [proof 4]
      • This is the analog of "if a sequence converges to then so does every subsequence."
    2. If is a cluster point of then is a cluster point of
      • This is the analog of "if is a cluster point of some subsequence, then is a cluster point of the original sequence."
  2. if and only if for any finer prefilter there exists some even more fine prefilter such that [38]
    • This is the analog of "a sequence converges to if and only if every subsequence has a sub–subsequence that converges to "
  3. is a cluster point of if and only if there exists some finer prefilter such that
    • This is the analog of " is a cluster point of a sequence if and only if it has a subsequence that converges to " (that is, if and only if is a subsequential limit).

Non–equivalence of subnets and subordinate filters

A subset of a preordered space is frequent or cofinal in if for every there exists some If contains a tail of then is said to be eventual or eventually in ; explicitly, this means that there exists some (that is, ). A subset is eventual if and only if its complement is not frequent (which is termed infrequent).[43] A map between two preordered sets is order–preserving if whenever

Subnets in the sense of Willard and subnets in the sense of Kelley are the most commonly used definitions of "subnet."[43] The first definition of a subnet was introduced by John L. Kelley in 1955.[43] Stephen Willard introduced his own variant of Kelley's definition of subnet in 1970.[43] AA–subnets were introduced independently by Smiley (1957), Aarnes and Andenaes (1972), and Murdeshwar (1983); AA–subnets were studied in great detail by Aarnes and Andenaes but they are not often used.[43]

Let be nets. Then[43]
  1. is a Willard–subnet of or a subnet in the sense of Willard if there exists an order–preserving map such that is cofinal in
  2. is a Kelley–subnet of or a subnet in the sense of Kelley if there exists a map and whenever is eventually in then is eventually in
  3. is an AA–subnet of or a subnet in the sense of Aarnes and Andenaes if any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
    1. If is eventually in is eventually in
    2. For any subset mesh, then so do
    3. For any subset

Kelley did not require the map to be order preserving while the definition of an AA–subnet does away entirely with any map between the two nets' domains and instead focuses entirely on − the nets' common codomain. Every Willard–subnet is a Kelley–subnet and both are AA–subnets.[43] In particular, if is a Willard–subnet or a Kelley–subnet of then

AA–subnets have a defining characterization that immediately shows that they are fully interchangeable with sub(ordinate)filters.[43][44] Explicitly, what is meant is that the following statement is true for AA–subnets:

If are prefilters then is an AA–subnet of

If "AA–subnet" is replaced by "Willard–subnet" or "Kelley–subnet" then the above statement becomes false. In particular, the problem is that the following statement is in general false:

False statement: If are prefilters such that is a Kelley–subnet of

Since every Willard–subnet is a Kelley–subnet, this statement remains false if the word "Kelley–subnet" is replaced with "Willard–subnet".

  • Counter example: For all let Let which is a proper π–system, and let where both families are prefilters on the natural numbers Because is to as a subsequence is to a sequence. So ideally, should be a subnet of Let be the domain of so contains a cofinal subset that is order isomorphic to and consequently contains neither a maximal nor greatest element. Let is both a maximal and greatest element of The directed set also contains a subset that is order isomorphic to (because it contains which contains such a subset) but no such subset can be cofinal in because of the maximal element Consequently, any order–preserving map must be eventually constant (with value ) where is then a greatest element of the range Because of this, there can be no order preserving map that satisfies the conditions required for to be a Willard–subnet of (because the range of such a map cannot be cofinal in ). Suppose for the sake of contradiction that there exists a map such that is eventually in for all Because there exist such that For every because is eventually in it is necessary that In particular, if then which by definition is equivalent to which is false. Consequently, is not a Kelley–subnet of [44]

If "subnet" is defined to mean Willard–subnet or Kelley–subnet then nets and filters are not completely interchangeable because there exists a filter–sub(ordinate)filter relationships that cannot be expressed in terms of a net–subnet relationship between the two induced nets. In particular, the problem is that Kelley–subnets and Willard–subnets are not fully interchangeable with subordinate filters. If the notion of "subnet" is not used or if "subnet" is defined to mean AA–subnet, then this ceases to be a problem and so it becomes correct to say that nets and filters are interchangeable. Despite the fact that AA–subnets do not have the problem that Willard and Kelley subnets have, they are not widely used or known about.[43][44]

Topologies and prefilters

Throughout, is a topological space.

Examples of relationships between filters and topologies

Bases and prefilters

Let be a family of sets that covers and define for every The definition of a base for some topology can be immediately reworded as: is a base for some topology on if and only if is a filter base for every If is a topology on and then the definitions of is a basis (resp. subbase) for can be reworded as:

is a base (resp. subbase) for if and only if for every is a filter base (resp. filter subbase) that generates the neighborhood filter of at

Neighborhood filters

The archetypical example of a filter is the set of all neighborhoods of a point in a topological space. Any neighborhood basis of a point in (or of a subset of) a topological space is a prefilter. In fact, the definition of a neighborhood base can be equivalently restated as: "a neighborhood base is any prefilter that is equivalent the neighborhood filter."

Neighborhood bases at points are examples of prefilters that are fixed but may or may not be principal. If has its usual topology and if then any neighborhood filter base of is fixed by (in fact, it is even true that ) but is not principal since In contrast, a topological space has the discrete topology if and only if the neighborhood filter of every point is a principal filter generated by exactly one point. This shows that a non–principal filter on an infinite set is not necessarily free.

The neighborhood filter of every point in topological space is fixed since its kernel contains (and possibly other points if, for instance, is not a T1 space). This is also true of any neighborhood basis at For any point in a T1 space (for example, a Hausdorff space), the kernel of the neighborhood filter of is equal to the singleton set

However, it is possible for a neighborhood filter at a point to be principal but not discrete (that is, not principal at a single point). A neighborhood basis of a point in a topological space is principal if and only if the kernel of is an open set. If in addition the space is T1 then so that this basis is principal if and only if is an open set.

Generating topologies from filters and prefilters

Suppose is not empty (and ). If is a filter on then is a topology on but the converse is in general false. This shows that in a sense, filters are almost topologies. Topologies of the form where is an ultrafilter on are an even more specialized subclass of such topologies; they have the property that every proper subset is either open or closed, but (unlike the discrete topology) never both. These spaces are, in particular, examples of door spaces.

If is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, π–system, proper) on then the same is true of both and the set of all possible unions of one or more elements of If is closed under finite intersections then the set is a topology on with both being bases for it. If the π–system covers then both are also bases for If is a topology on then is a prefilter (or equivalently, a π–system) if and only if it has the finite intersection property (that is, it is a filter subbase), in which case a subset will be a basis for if and only if is equivalent to in which case will be a prefilter.

Topologies on directed sets and net convergence

Let be a non–empty directed set and let where Then is a prefilter that covers and if is totally ordered then is also closed under finite intersections. This particular prefilter forms a base for a topology on in which all sets of the form are also open. The same is true of the topology where is the filter on generated by With this topology, convergent nets can be viewed as continuous functions in the following way. Let be a topological space, let let be a net in and let denote the set of all open neighborhoods of If the net converges to then is necessarily continuous although in general, the converse is false (for example, consider if is constant and not equal to ). But if in addition to continuity, the preimage under of every is not empty, then the net will necessarily converge to In this way, the empty set is all that separates net convergence and continuity.

Another way in which a convergent nets can be viewed as continuous functions is, for any given and net to first extend the net to a new net where is a new symbol, by defining for every If is endowed with the topology

then (that is, the net converges to ) if and only if is a continuous function. Moreover, is always a dense subset of

Topological properties and prefilters

Throughout will be a topological space with

Neighborhoods and topologies

The neighborhood filter of a non–empty subset in a topological space is equal to the intersection of all neighborhood filters of all points in [28] If then is open in if and only if whenever is a filter on and then

Suppose are topologies on Then is finer than (that is, ) if and only if whenever is a filter on if then [39] Consequently, if and only if for every filter and every if and only if [29] However, it is possible that while also for every filter converges to some point of if and only if converges to some point of [29]

Closure

If then the following are equivalent:

  1. is a limit point of the prefilter (that is, ).
  2. There exists a prefilter such that
  3. There exists a prefilter such that [42]
  4. is a cluster point of the prefilter
  5. The prefilter meshes with the neighborhood filter
  6. The prefilter meshes with some (or equivalently, with every) prefilter of

The following are equivalent:

  1. is a limit points of
  2. There exists a prefilter such that [42]
Closed sets

If is not empty then the following are equivalent:

  1. is a closed subset of
  2. If is a prefilter on such that then
  3. If is a prefilter on such that is an accumulation points of then [42]
  4. If is such that the neighborhood filter meshes with then
    • The proof of this characterization depends the ultrafilter lemma, which depends on the axiom of choice.

Hausdorffness

The following are equivalent:

  1. is Hausdorff.
  2. Every prefilter on converges to at most one point in [8]
  3. The above statement but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter, ultra prefilter, ultrafilter.[8]

Compactness

As discussed in this article, the Ultrafilter Lemma is closely related to many important theorems involving compactness.

The following are equivalent:

  1. is a compact space.
  2. Every ultrafilter on converges to at least one point in
    • That this condition implies compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma. That compactness implies this condition can be proven without the ultrafilter lemma (or even the axiom of choice).
  3. The above statement but with the words "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter, ultrafilter.[45]
  4. For every filter there exists a filter such that and converges to some point of
  5. For every prefilter there exists a prefilter such that and converges to some point of
  6. Every maximal (i.e. ultra) prefilter on converges to at least one point in [8]
  7. The above statement but with the words "maximal prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: prefilter, filter, ultra prefilter, ultrafilter.
  8. Every prefilter on has at least one cluster point in [8]
    • That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.
  9. Alexander subbase theorem: There exists a subbase such that every cover of by sets in has a finite subcover.
    • That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.

If is topological space and is the set of all complements of compact subsets of then is a filter on if and only if is not compact.

Theorem[45]If is a filter on a compact space is the set of cluster points of then every neighborhood of belongs to Thus a filter on a compact Hausdorff space converges if and only if it has a single cluster point.

Continuity

Let is a map between topological spaces

Given the following are equivalent:

  1. is continuous at
  2. Definition: For every neighborhood of there exists some neighborhood of such that
  3. is a filter base for ; that is, the upward closure of is equal to [42]
  4. [42]
  5. If is a filter on such that then
  6. The above statement but with the word "filter" replaced by "prefilter".

The following are equivalent:

  1. is continuous.
  2. If is a prefilter on such that then
  3. If is a limit point of a prefilter then is a limit point of
  4. Any one of the above two statements but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter.

If is a prefilter on is a cluster point of is continuous, then is a cluster point in of the prefilter [39]

Products

Suppose is a non–empty family of non–empty topological spaces and that is a family of prefilters where each is a prefilter on Then the product of these prefilters (defined above) is a prefilter on the product space which as usual, is endowed with the product topology.

If then if and only if

Suppose are topological spaces, is a prefilter on having as a cluster point, and is a prefilter on having as a cluster point. Then is a cluster point of in the product space [39] However, if then there exist sequences such that both of these sequences have a cluster point in but the sequence does not have a cluster point in [39]

Example application: The ultrafilter lemma along with the axioms of ZF imply Tychonoff's theorem for compact Hausdorff spaces:

Proof

Let be compact Hausdorff topological spaces. Assume that the ultrafilter lemma holds (because of the Hausdorff assumption, this proof does not need the full strength of the axiom of choice; the ultrafilter lemma suffices). Let be given the product topology (which makes a Hausdorff space) and for every let denote this product's projections. If then is compact and the proof is complete so assume Despite the fact that because the axiom of choice is not assumed, the projection maps are not guaranteed to be surjective.

Let be an ultrafilter on and for every let denote the ultrafilter on generated by the ultra prefilter Because is compact and Hausdorff, the ultrafilter converges to a unique limit point (because of 's uniqueness, this definition does not require the axiom of choice). Let where satisfies for every The characterization of convergence in the product topology that was given above implies that Thus every ultrafilter on converges to some point of which implies that is compact (recall that this implication's proof only required the ultrafilter lemma).

Examples of applications of prefilters

Uniformities and Cauchy prefilters

A uniform space is a set equipped with a filter on that has certain properties. A base or fundamental system of entourages is a prefilter on whose upward closure is a uniform space. A prefilter on a uniform space with uniformity is called a Cauchy prefilter if for every entourage there exists some that is –small, which means that A uniform space is called complete (resp. sequentially complete) if every Cauchy prefilter (resp. every elementary Cauchy prefilter) on converges to at least one point of A minimal Cauchy filter is a minimal element (with respect to or equivalently, to ) of the set of all Cauchy filters on Examples of minimal Cauchy filters include the neighborhood filter of any point

Uniform spaces were the result of attempts to generalize notions such as "uniform continuity" and "uniform convergence" that are present in metric spaces. Every topological vector space, and more generally, every topological group can be made into a uniform space in a canonical way. Every uniformity also generates a canonical induced topology. Filters and prefilters play an important role in the theory of uniform spaces. For example, the completion of a Hausdorff uniform space (even if it is not metrizable) is typically constructed by using minimal Cauchy filters. Nets are less ideal for this construction because their domains are extremely varied (for example, the class of all Cauchy nets is not a set); sequences cannot be used in the general case because the topology might not be metrizable, first–countable, or even sequential. The set of all minimal Cauchy filters on a Hausdorff topological vector space (TVS) can made into a vector space and topologized in such a way that it becomes a completion of (with the assignment becoming a linear topological embedding that identifies as a dense vector subspace of this completion).

Convergence of nets of sets

There is often a personal preference of nets over filters or filters over nets. This example shows that the choice between nets and filters is not a dichotomy by combining them together.

A net of sets in or a net of subsets of refers to a net in the power set of that is, a net of sets in is a function from a non–empty directed set into However, a "net in " will always refer to a net valued in and never to a net valued in although for emphasis or contrast, a net in may also be referred to as a net of points in . A net of sets in is called a net of singleton (resp. non–empty, finite, compact, etc.) sets in if every has this property. Similarly, is called eventually empty (resp. non–empty, finite, compact, etc.) if there is some index such that this is true of for every index

The following definition generalizes the notion of the set of tails of a net of points in to nets of subsets of

Suppose is a net of sets in Define for every index the tail of starting at to be the set

and define the set or family of tails generated by to be the family
The family is a prefilter if and only if it does not contain the empty set, which is equivalent to not being eventually empty; in this case the upward closure in of this prefilter of tails is called the filter of tails or eventuality filter in generated by A net (of sets or points) is eventually contained in a set if and only if so is eventually empty if and only if

Nets of sets arise naturally when pulling back nets in a function's codomain. If is a map and is a net of sets (or of points) then let and that is, denotes the net of sets defined by The tail of starting at an index is equal to and similarly, the tail of starting at is Consequently, where this family if a prefilter if and only if is a prefilter; similarly, One useful consequence of this definition is that is a prefilter if and only if cofinally intersects (or for points, is cofinally in) meaning that for every index there is some such that (where this intersection means if is a point instead of a set). In particular, eventually being contained in (meaning that for some ) is not a necessary condition for to be a prefilter. So even if a net of points in cannot be pulled back by to a net of points in (say because it is not entirely/eventually in the image of ), it is nevertheless still possible to talk about the net of sets and its properties (such as convergence or clustering).

Convergence and clustering

Consideration of the following bijective correspondence leads naturally to the following definition, which is completely analogous to the previously given definition of the tails of a net (of points) in

(Nets of points Nets of singleton sets): Every net of points in can be uniquely associated with the canonical net of singleton sets and conversely, every net of singleton sets in is uniquely associated with a canonical net of points (defined in the obvious way). The tail of starting at an index is equal to that of (that is, to ); consequently, This makes it apparent that the following definition of "convergence of a net of sets" in is indeed a generalization of the original definition of "convergence of a net of points" in (because if and only if ); similarly, a net of points clusters at a given point or subset (according to the original definition) if and only if its associated net of singleton sets clusters at (according to the definition below).

A net of sets is said to converge in to a given point or subset of written if which recall was defined to mean that Explicitly, this happens if and only if for every neighborhood of there exists some index such that Similarly, is said to cluster at a given point or subset of if meshes with (written ); explicitly, this means that for every index and neighborhood of

Every net of sets that is eventually empty converges to every point/subset. However, a net of sets converges to if and only if it is eventually empty. No net of sets clusters at If a net of sets converges to then it will cluster at if and only if it is not eventually empty (which implies ). If is a net in then is a net of sets in and for any point or subset of converges to (respectively, clusters at) in if and only if this is true of This statement remains true if is instead a net of sets. If is a map and is a net (of points or of sets) then converges to (respectively, clusters at) some given point or subset of if and only if every neighborhood of it contains (respectively, intersects) some set of the form Moreover, the net converges in to some given point or subset if and only if this is true of

Applications

Some applications are now given showing how nets of sets can be used to characterize various properties. In the statements below, the map is not necessarily surjective and is a point and is nets of points in

  • A map is closed (meaning it sends closed sets to closed subset of ) if and only if whenever then This characterization remains true if are allowed to be sets (instead of restricted to being points) such that
    Proof

    Assume is closed and If then is in the open set so that implies that is eventually empty and thus that in So assume and let be an open neighborhood of in It remains to show that for some index Since is closed, is an open neighborhood of in so there must exists some index such that This implies where the right hand side is a subset of as desired.

    For the converse, assume that implies Let be closed and assume it is not empty. Let be a net in (meaning for all ) and let be such that It remains to show that The hypotheses guarantee that The fact that every fiber is not empty and that these fibers converge to imply that Since is open, were it true that then there would exist some index such that which is impossible since for every index Thus so there is some which proves that

  • A map is open (meaning it sends open sets to open subset of ) if and only if whenever is a point of and is a net that clusters at in then clusters at in This characterization remains true if are allowed to be sets.
    Proof

    For the non-trivial direction, suppose that is not an open map. Pick an open subset such that is not open in where non-openness means that there is some point such that is not a neighborhood of in Explicitly, this means that for every neighborhood of in which guarantees the existence of some Let denote the neighborhood filter of in and direct it by to make into a net that converges to in which implies that clusters at in Because there is some But does not clusters at since for every

  • A map is open if and only if whenever then any closed subset of that contains will necessarily also contain (A set contains means that for every index ) This characterization remains true if is allowed to be a net of sets that is not eventually empty (instead of being a net of points) and remains a point such that The same is true of the quotient map characterization below.
    • In comparison, by the closure characterization of continuity, is continuous if and only if whenever then any closed subset of that contains will necessarily also contain
    Proof

    If is any subset then it is readily verified that This implies that a map is open if and only if whenever is closed in then is closed in This characterization of "open map" combined with the convergent net characterization of closed sets produces the desired conclusion: is open if and only if whenever and is a closed subset of that contains then necessarily

  • A continuous surjection is a quotient map if and only if whenever then any saturated closed subset of that contains will necessarily also contain (A set is saturated if )
  • A subset is closed in if and only if for every point and every net of subsets of that is not eventually empty, if then
  • A map is continuous if and only if whenever a net of points or sets in converges to a point or set then
    Proof

    The proof is essentially identical to the usual proof involving only nets of points. One direction (that whose conclusion is that is continuous) only requires consideration of nets of points and so it is omitted. So suppose that the map is continuous and that Let be an open neighborhood of in Then is an open neighborhood of in so there exists some index such that Thus as desired.

  • If is continuous and is a net of sets (or points) in that clusters at (respectively, converges to) some given point or subset of then clusters at (respectively, converges to) in

Topologizing the set of prefilters

Starting with nothing more than a set it is possible to topologize the set

of all filter bases on with the Stone topology, which is named after Marshall Harvey Stone.

To reduce confusion, this article will adhere to the following notational conventions:

  • Lower case letters for elements
  • Upper case letters for subsets
  • Upper case calligraphy letters for subsets (or equivalently, for elements such as prefilters).
  • Upper case double–struck letters for subsets

For every let

where [note 15] These sets will be the basic open subsets of the Stone topology. If then

From this inclusion, it is possible to deduce all of the subset inclusions displayed below with the exception of [note 16] For all

where in particular, the equality shows that the family is a –system that forms a basis for a topology on called the Stone topology. It is henceforth assumed that carries this topology and that any subset of carries the induced subspace topology.

In contrast to most other general constructions of topologies (for example, the product, quotient, subspace topologies, etc.), this topology on was defined without using anything other than the set there were no preexisting structures or assumptions on so this topology is completely independent of everything other than (and its subsets).

The following criteria can be used for checking for points of closure and neighborhoods. If then:

  • Closure in : belongs to the closure of if and only if
  • Neighborhoods in : is a neighborhood of if and only if there exists some such that (that is, such that for all ).

It will be henceforth assumed that because otherwise and the topology is which is uninteresting.

Subspace of ultrafilters

The set of ultrafilters on (with the subspace topology) is a Stone space, meaning that it is compact, Hausdorff, and totally disconnected. If has the discrete topology then the map defined by sending to the principal ultrafilter at is a topological embedding whose image is a dense subset of (see the article Stone–Čech compactification for more details).

Relationships between topologies on and the Stone topology on

Every induces a canonical map defined by which sends to the neighborhood filter of The map is injective if and only if (that is, a Kolmogorov space) and moreover, if then Thus every can be identified with the canonical map which allows to be canonically identified as a subset of (as a side note, it is now possible to place on and thus also on the topology of pointwise convergence on so that it now makes sense to talk about things such as topologies converging pointwise on ). For every the surjection is continuous, closed, and open. In particular, for every topology the map is a topological embedding.

In addition, if is a map such that (which is true of for instance), then for every the set is a neighborhood of (where has the subspace topology inherited from ).

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Sequences and nets in a space are maps from directed sets like the natural number, which in general maybe entirely unrelated to the set and so they, and consequently also their notions of convergence, are not intrinsic to
  2. ^ Technically, any infinite subfamily of this set of tails is enough to characterize this sequence's convergence. But in general, unless indicated otherwise, the set of all tails is taken unless there is some reason to do otherwise.
  3. ^ Indeed, net convergence is defined using neighborhood filters while (pre)filters are directed sets with respect to so it is difficult to keep these notions completely separate.
  4. ^ a b The terms "Filter base" and "Filter" are used if and only if
  5. ^ Indeed, in both the cases appearing on the right is precisely what makes "greater", for if are related by some binary relation (meaning that ) then whichever one of appears on the right is said to be greater than or equal to the one that appears on the left with respect to (or less verbosely, "–greater than or equal to").
  6. ^ More generally, for any real numbers satisfying where
  7. ^ If This property and the fact that is nonempty and proper if and only if actually allows for the construction of even more examples of prefilters, because if is any prefilter (resp. filter subbase, π–system) then so is
  8. ^ It may be shown that if is any family such that then is a prefilter if and only if for all real there exist real such that
  9. ^ For instance, one sense in which a net could be interpreted as being "maximally deep" is if all important properties related to (such as convergence for example) of any subnet is completely determined by in all topologies on In this case and its subnet become effectively indistinguishable (at least topologically) if one's information about them is limited to only that which can be described in solely in terms of and directly related sets (such as its subsets).
  10. ^ The π–system generated by (resp. by ) is a prefilter whose elements are finite unions of open (resp. closed) intervals having endpoints in with two of these intervals being of the forms (resp. ) where ; in the case of it is possible for one or more of these closed intervals to be singleton sets (that is, degenerate closed intervals).
  11. ^ For an example of how this failure can happen, consider the case where there exists some such that both and its complement in contains at least two distinct points.
  12. ^ Suppose has more than one point, is a constant map, and then will consist of all non–empty subsets of
  13. ^ The set equality holds more generally: if the family of sets then the family of tails of the map (defined by ) is equal to
  14. ^ Explicitly, the partial order on induced by equality refers to the diagonal which is a homogeneous relation on that makes into a partially ordered set. If this partial order is denoted by the more familiar symbol (that is, define ) then for any which shows that (and thus also ) is nothing more than a new symbol for equality on that is, The notation is used because it avoids the unnecessary introduction of a new symbol for the diagonal.
  15. ^ As a side note, had the definitions of "filter" and "prefilter" not required propriety then the degenerate dual ideal would have been a prefilter on so that in particular, with
  16. ^ This is because the inclusion is the only one in the sequence below whose proof uses the defining assumption that

Proofs

  1. ^ Let be a filter on that is not an ultrafilter. If is such that has the finite intersection property (because if ) so that by the ultrafilter lemma, there exists some ultrafilter such that (so in particular, ). Intersecting all such proves that
  2. ^ a b To prove that mesh, let Because (resp. because ), there exists some where by assumption so If is a filter subbase and if then taking implies that If then there are such that and now This shows that is a filter subbase.
  3. ^ This is because if are prefilters on then
  4. ^ By definition, Since transitivity implies

Citations

  1. ^ H. Cartan, "Théorie des filtres", CR Acad. Paris, 205, (1937) 595–598.
  2. ^ H. Cartan, "Filtres et ultrafiltres", CR Acad. Paris, 205, (1937) 777–779.
  3. ^ Wilansky 2013, p. 44.
  4. ^ a b c d e Schechter 1996, pp. 155–171.
  5. ^ Howes 1995, pp. 83–92.
  6. ^ a b c d e f Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 27–29.
  7. ^ a b c d e f Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 33–35.
  8. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t Narici & Beckenstein 2011, pp. 2–7.
  9. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r Császár 1978, pp. 53–65.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 27–54.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y Bourbaki 1987, pp. 57–68.
  12. ^ a b Schubert 1968, pp. 48–71.
  13. ^ a b c Narici & Beckenstein 2011, pp. 3–4.
  14. ^ a b c d e f Dugundji 1966, pp. 215–221.
  15. ^ a b c Wilansky 2013, p. 5.
  16. ^ a b c Dolecki & Mynard 2016, p. 10.
  17. ^ a b c d e f g h Schechter 1996, pp. 100–130.
  18. ^ Császár 1978, pp. 82–91.
  19. ^ a b c d Dugundji 1966, pp. 211–213.
  20. ^ Schechter 1996, p. 100.
  21. ^ Császár 1978, pp. 53–65, 82–91.
  22. ^ Arkhangel'skii & Ponomarev 1984, pp. 7–8.
  23. ^ Joshi 1983, p. 244.
  24. ^ a b c Dugundji 1966, p. 212.
  25. ^ a b c Wilansky 2013, pp. 44–46.
  26. ^ Castillo, Jesus M. F.; Montalvo, Francisco (January 1990), "A Counterexample in Semimetric Spaces" (PDF), Extracta Mathematicae, 5 (1): 38–40
  27. ^ Schaefer & Wolff 1999, pp. 1–11.
  28. ^ a b c d Bourbaki 1987, pp. 129–133.
  29. ^ a b c d e f g Wilansky 2008, pp. 32–35.
  30. ^ a b c d Dugundji 1966, pp. 219–221.
  31. ^ a b Jech 2006, pp. 73–89.
  32. ^ a b Császár 1978, pp. 53–65, 82–91, 102–120.
  33. ^ a b Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 37–39.
  34. ^ a b c Arkhangel'skii & Ponomarev 1984, pp. 20–22.
  35. ^ a b c d e f g h Császár 1978, pp. 102–120.
  36. ^ Bourbaki 1989, pp. 68–83.
  37. ^ a b c Dixmier 1984, pp. 13–18.
  38. ^ a b c d e f g h Bourbaki 1987, pp. 68–74.
  39. ^ a b c d e f g h i Bourbaki 1987, pp. 132–133.
  40. ^ a b Kelley 1975, pp. 65–72.
  41. ^ Bruns G., Schmidt J.,Zur Aquivalenz von Moore-Smith-Folgen und Filtern, Math. Nachr. 13 (1955), 169-186.
  42. ^ a b c d e f g Dugundji 1966, pp. 211–221.
  43. ^ a b c d e f g h i Schechter 1996, pp. 157–168.
  44. ^ a b c Clark, Pete L. (18 October 2016). "Convergence" (PDF). math.uga.edu/. Retrieved 18 August 2020.
  45. ^ a b Bourbaki 1987, pp. 83–85.

References